Can you do something terrible (hit a child) with a good intention (disciplining the child) and expect to be praised as a result of performing a bad act (child behaves according to expectations) ?
A friend of mine sent me a wonderful link
on the subject –
an add about children copying which is brilliant. If you are going to
listen to one thing on Youtube today, well listen to Dazed and Confused,
after all, it’s Friday and you need to get a groove on already. But if you’re
listening to two things....well, you know.
We’ve
talked about the Heinz Dilemma before and how it expresses whether a person
is wrong to steal, over-charge and the like for medicine;
A woman was near death from a
special kind of cancer. There was one drug that the doctors thought might save
her. It was a form of radium that a druggist in the same town had recently
discovered. The drug was expensive to make, but the druggist was charging ten
times what the drug cost him to produce. He paid $200 for the radium and
charged $2,000 for a small dose of the drug. The sick woman's husband, Heinz,
went to everyone he knew to borrow the money, but he could only get together
about $ 1,000, which is half of what it cost. He told the druggist that his
wife was dying and asked him to sell it cheaper or let him pay later. But the
druggist said, "No, I discovered the drug and I'm going to make money from
it." So Heinz got desperate and broke into the man's store to steal the
drug for his wife. Should Heinz have broken into the laboratory to steal the drug
for his wife? Why or why not?
But it can be complicated by a few things.
Firstly, is action more morally meaningful
than inaction? Consider the two neighbours, Alf and Deb; both live in absolute
luxury by virtue of the fact that they are the trusted protector of their very
wealthy, multi-billionaire, two year old, orphaned niece. If Alf’s niece, or
Deb’s niece die, Alf and/or Deb will inherit billions as the only remaining relative.
Alf and Deb both absolutely hate their respective bratty nieces and resent
looking after them.
One day Deb has had enough and, while her
niece is in the bath, grabs her head and gently but forcefully pushes her under
the water and her niece drowns.
As luck would have it, at exactly the same
time Alf is bathing his niece and leaves for a second to grab a towel. When he
returns, he noticed that his niece has accidentally slipped, fell, hit her head
on the side of the bath and is currently not able to breathe. Alf doesn’t do
anything. He steps back and waits for the bath to, of its own actions, kill his
niece.
Both Alf and Deb are now billionaires and
free from the trials of looking after their nieces. But is Alf’s conduct any
less than Debs? Does it matter that he didn’t actually do anything to end the
life of his niece?
Let’s warp the story a little more. Say
neither niece die. Say that both Deb and Alf recanted at the last second and brought
their kin back to life. But in this instance, their nieces both had book clots
in their head which, being held under water for a little minute, were cured by
the pressure of the water rushing in and blasting the clots out through their
eyes. Should we praise either of them for curing the blood clots of their kin?
Should Deb be praised more than Alf due to her actively changing actions?
Now, the more smarmy in our merry band will
be shaking you fists at me screaming “This
is the Doctrine of Double Effect and has been answered by everyone from St
Augustine to Jerry Seinfeld.” And you’d be right, it has, but my favourite
version of it; The Trolley Dilemma and the Kill Whitey Project, is where this
blog is going today. And hey – if you already know the answer, skip ahead, but
don’t spoil it for the person sitting beside you.
The essential question is – ‘what is the
role of reason and emotion in moral questioning?’ We like to call ourselves
advanced and say that emotion is bad and reason, devoid of emotion , equates to
an advanced morality. Especially when you look at people like Piaget, Kohlberg
and those following, there is this linear approach to moral development. The
trolley dilemma and the kill whitey project present this wonderfully archaic,
yet researched viewpoint that our morality is just as much a slave to our
emotions, especially emotions like disgust, as they were to the hypothetical
caveman who started the whole debate. It states that we are not further developed
by our reasoning faculties at all.
The question is very much about Normative reasoning,
of which there are two general schools of thought: consequentialist and deontological, albeit there
is a third school – virtue ethics which has a considerably better answer to
these questions, but it’s not a task for us today.
The basic version of the trolley dilemma
asks would you kill a man in a particular situation, and then presents a
situation where this may be acceptable.
In the first instance, you are out walking
one day and see a dilapidated train track. You follow it for a while and find
two tunnels up ahead: one with five workmen in it, the other with only one workman.
Then all of a sudden, an out of control train comes screaming down the track.
You look down and, as luck would have it, you are positioned right beside the
track changer which controls which tunnel the out of control train is headed.
You notice that it is headed toward the tunnel with the five men in it. So do
you act? Do you change the track to kill one man, deliberately and unashamedly
just to save the lives of five?
Funnily enough, more than 90% of people
faced with this dilemma would switch the tracks and kill one person.
In its second incarnation, the same situation
happens, except rather than standing next to the track changer, you are
standing on a footbridge on top of the entrance to the tunnel. You realise that
you might be able to jump down in front of the train to stop it, but you would
be way too skinny. Thankfully, standing beside you is a portly gentleman whose
girth would easily stop the train. Do you push the man off the footbridge? Do
you kill a man to save the lives of five?
In answering this question, most people say
the exact opposite; almost everyone would let the five men die.
A third incarnation is where you are a
doctor on duty in an ER, rushed and over-worked. A motorcycle accident victim
comes in. He is pretty much dead, but there is a chance that an emergency
procedure to open up his skull/brain area to relieve pressure has a 2% chance
to save his life. It is a highly risky operation and no one would be the wiser
if you accidentally slipped by half a millimetre and cut the wrong cord,
killing the motorcyclist. You have five other patients, one who needs a lung
transplant, one who needs a heart transplant, one who needs kidneys etc. And they
need this within the next few hours or they will die. The motorcycle accident victim
is a perfect match for all five patients and will most likely live in a
brain-dead comma for a few days if left unoperated. Do you kill the
motorcyclist? Do you perform the operation to the best of your abilities? Do
you kill one man to save the lives of five?
There has been a great deal of research
dedicated to trying to say why this is the case; from people being brain
scanned while making these choices, to theories about our evolutionary background
failing to come to terms with the significance of a switch.
Our sense of highly developed moral
reasoning would say something like “the end never justifies the means” or perhaps
“do the act that results in the least net harm” or something similar.
Then the Trolley Dilemma goes through a fat
elvis stage; race and nationality are brought in. People are in a lifeboat
which has one too many persons in it. You draw straws as to who has to leave
(and drown). It comes up Tyrone Paton gets pushed off.
Is this moral? Does saving the lives of the five men on the boat justify
killing Tyrone. Almost all liberal voters would say no, almost all conservative
voters would say yes.
In a second incarnation, you draw straws as
to who gets pushed off and Chip Elsworth the Third’s name comes up. He gets
pushed off the boat and drowns to save the lives of the five remaining passengers.
Is this a moral choice? Is the killing of one man justified by the saving of
five lives? Most liberal voters would say yes, most conservative voters would
say no.
In further warps of the same logical
problem;
·
is the killing of innocent civilians
during a military campaign justified to end a war/restore peace in the
situation where civilian casualties are minimised, but expected. In one
setting, it is Western troops that are doing the fighting, and Iraqi civilians
doing the dying; in another setting, it is Iraqi insurgence that are doing the
fighting, Western Troops that are doing the dying.
·
is there a limit to the freedom
of speech? Can someone burn an American flag? Can someone draw a malicious
cartoon of the Prophet Mohammed? Which is freedom of speech and which has gone
too far.
In these examples, the conservative/liberal
divide comes through loud and strong: a liberal would have no problem killing
Western Troops and burning the American Flag, but would see killing Iraqis and
laughing at Mohammed as unacceptable. Conservatives go the opposite way.
Then something really interesting happens:
people are given the same dilemmas to answer, but rather than political
affiliation, they are first asked to unscramble a word. One group is given a
word that is synonymous with patriotism, the other a word that is synonymous
with multiculturalism. The findings, quite amazingly mirror the conservative
responses in those given patriotism words, and the liberals in those given
multiculturalism words.
What’s even more amazing is that people,
when alerted to their moral inconsistencies: who will agree with the bombing of
Hiroshima while at the same time being adamant that the end never justifies the
means etc will change and adapt their understanding to new stimuli.
But irregardless, the findings of
all this seems to be that we are not liberal, conservative, deontologists,
consequentialists or the like; we have a morality like a bag of tricks, to be
pulled out when we find it appropriate. This begs the question: why do we chose
one moral principle in some settings, while find it abhorrent in other
settings?
The answer, weak though it may be, is that
we favour connectedness to a familiar view. We will do our best to preserve our
own understanding of the world, to the point of absurdity at times, but we
greatly exaggerate and over-estimate our own abilities. The confirmation bias,
or as I’ve always said, “the one thing that unites us as humans is that
everyone thinks that they are an above average driver.”
So is it right or wrong to hit children? I
would say it is never acceptable...but why? Firstly, it doesn’t work, secondly
it is violence, and violence is always wrong. Violence
is always wrong. The only thing to be learned from it is to avoid it because it
is the point where reason, thought...indeed humanity itself stops working.
But then what about a situation where someone about my size was beating up a
kid, an elderly couple or something and they weren’t listening to reason? Is it
wrong for me to hit that person a few times...bugger, there goes that theory. What
if the aggressor is considerably smaller than me?
What if it is the case that most people would pull the level to kill a person, but not push a fat man onto the tracks is because our evolutionary make up hasn't dealt with the concept of switches and buttons yet, however, we all know too well the effect of direct violence. Perhaps. Perhaps it is because we have never seen the effect of a switch, yet all of us have seen the effect of being pushed, in the school yard or in the workplace. Some of us know the effect of doing the pushing.
Then maybe it is because we have to see the man being pushed, we have to see the motorcyclist die. We see him watching us and dying. That breads the association that we fear and are disgusted with.
Is it just a
case that I am not a pacifist, I see violence being used and chose to identify
with the child that was hit, the child that will learn to mistrust these people, fear them, hate then
and grow distant from them where other people would associate with the
authoritarian parent figure and pretend that they learned respect from that
action. Let’s just take that as a comment hey?
This
post’s groovy, identity seeking quote:
'“People should
either be caressed or crushed. If you do them minor damage they will get their
revenge; but if you cripple them there is nothing they can do. If you need to
injure someone, do it in such a way that you do not have to fear their
vengeance.”
This
post’s lame joke: `
A man and a woman who had never met before,
but who were both "married to other people," found themselves
assigned to the same sleeping room on a trans-continental train.
Though initially embarrassed and uneasy over sharing a room, they were both very tired and fell asleep quickly, he in the upper berth and she in the lower.
At 1:00 AM, the man leaned down and gently woke the woman saying, "Ma'am, I'm sorry to bother you, but would you be willing to reach into the closet to get me a second blanket? I'm awfully cold."
"I have a better idea," she replied. "Just for tonight, let's pretend that we're married."
"Wow! That's a great idea!", he exclaimed.
"Good," she replied. "Get your own damn blanket."
After a moment of silence, he farted.
Though initially embarrassed and uneasy over sharing a room, they were both very tired and fell asleep quickly, he in the upper berth and she in the lower.
At 1:00 AM, the man leaned down and gently woke the woman saying, "Ma'am, I'm sorry to bother you, but would you be willing to reach into the closet to get me a second blanket? I'm awfully cold."
"I have a better idea," she replied. "Just for tonight, let's pretend that we're married."
"Wow! That's a great idea!", he exclaimed.
"Good," she replied. "Get your own damn blanket."
After a moment of silence, he farted.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.